These paragraphs on existentialism from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy are quite interesting. Rather pertinent to my investigation of the links between materialism and existentialism, those being the intellectual-historical bookends, so to speak, of the fascinating series of highly neo-Platonic or Aristotelean intellectual movements from Romanticism to Modernism. (Yes, I'm very aware that materialism/scientific rationalism was also contemporary with all the movements from Romanticism to Modernism, but I'm considering it as most importantly a "predecessor" to all of them, since all of those movements can essentially be reduced to different ways of responding to materialism.) The last sentence is particularly relevant to my investigations along these lines.
"Sartre's slogan—“existence precedes
essence”—may serve to introduce what is most distinctive
of existentialism, namely, the idea that no general, non-formal
account of what it means to be human can be given, since that meaning
is decided in and through existing itself. Existence is
“self-making-in-a-situation” (Fackenheim 1961:37). In
contrast to other entities, whose essential properties are fixed by
the kind of entities they are, what is essential to a human
being—what makes her who she is—is not fixed by
her type but by what she makes of herself, who she
becomes. The
fundamental contribution of existential thought lies in the idea that
one's identity is constituted neither by nature nor by culture, since
to “exist” is precisely to constitute such an identity. It
is in light of this idea that key existential notions such as
facticity, transcendence (project), alienation, and authenticity must
be understood.
At first, it seems hard to understand how one can say much about
existence as such. Traditionally, philosophers have connected the
concept of existence with that of essence in such a way that the
former signifies merely the instantiation of the latter. If
“essence” designates what a thing is and
“existence” that it is, it follows that what is
intelligible about any given thing, what can be thought about it, will
belong to its essence. It is from essence in this sense—say,
human being as rational animal or imago Dei—that
ancient philosophy drew its prescriptions for an individual's way of
life, its estimation of the meaning and value of existence. Having an
essence meant that human beings could be placed within a larger whole,
a kosmos, that provided the standard for human
flourishing. Modern philosophy retained this framework even as it
abandoned the idea of a “natural place” for man in the
face of the scientific picture of an infinite, labyrinthine
universe. In what looks like a proto-existential move, Descartes
rejected the traditional essential definitions of man in favor of a
radical, first-person reflection on his own existence, the “I
am.” Nevertheless, he quickly reinstated the old model by
characterizing his existence as that of a substance determined by an
essential property, “thinking.” In contrast, Heidegger
proposes that “I” am “an entity whose what [essence]
is precisely to be and nothing but to be” (Heidegger 1985:110;
1962:67). Such an entity's existing cannot, therefore, be thought as
the instantiation of an essence, and consequently what it means to be
such an entity cannot be determined by appeal to pre-given frameworks
or systems—whether scientific, historical, or philosophical."
No comments:
Post a Comment